Muninn » Articles /blog But I fear more for Muninn... Tue, 23 Jun 2015 12:19:09 +0000 en-US hourly 1 http://wordpress.org/?v=4.2.2 Mark Twain, Traitor /blog/2008/02/mark-twain-traitor/ /blog/2008/02/mark-twain-traitor/#comments Thu, 07 Feb 2008 04:47:35 +0000 http://muninn.net/blog/2008/02/mark-twain-traitor.html Continue reading Mark Twain, Traitor]]> I really enjoyed an article I found by chance today about Twain’s attempts to narrate and justify his conduct during the US Civil War. From the closing paragraph:

My title, “Mark Twain, Traitor,” hails the Mark Twain who appears as such in his major work, whose text is constantly involved with the question of betrayal, of confused loyalties, not edifying us, giving us resolutions, just describing betrayal’s performance, its reasoning soliloquy. Huck guiltily betrays Uncle Jake in Tom Sawyer. and he desperately strives to betray Jim in Huckleberry Finn. “Mark Twain” is, of course, the key phrase in any letter of denunciation written for some police authority. Someone is not who he or she says he or she is. I report a Mark Twain whose post–Civil War nationalist identification is questionable, a Mark Twain at play with his progressive Unionist/Republican identification, at play with his reactionary Southern patrician identification, a Mark Twain who might be a double agent, or worse, a “free” agent, outside the rules of either comity, outside the several codes of honor, a marker, not the twain, not Southern, not Northern. I report a Mark Twain loose in his loyalties, Northern in his detestation of Southern moral turpitude, Southern in his contempt for the moral rectitude of the hypocritical Northeast, always an unreliable narrator, and for that reason always somewhere in rebellion, defying the positivities of both (particular) Confederacy and (universal) Union, their different disciplines. Mark that fellow. The name itself is a denunciation. How indeed did this transsectional Civil War rogue, migrant in all the sections of the country, never at home, always moving, become the principal icon of post–Civil War patriotic nationality? Mark Twain’s humor, William Dean Howells writes in My Mark Twain (1910), “is as simple in form and direct as the statesmanship of Lincoln or the generalship of Grant” (118). I have no idea what this means. Mark Twain’s humor is never simple and direct. In 1901, telling his Civil War story at Lincoln Birthday Dinner, amid the patriotic pieties, Mark Twain would again directly address the question: why did you desert the Civil War? Why did he not fight for Abraham Lincoln’s noble cause? Great humorist that he is, he tells the truth. It was the weather, Mark Twain says in 1901. You never saw such weather (Mark Twain Speaking 382).1

  1. Neil Schmitz “Mark Twain, Traitor” Arizona Quarterly: A Journal of American Literature, Culture, and Theory 63.4 (2007) 34-35
]]>
/blog/2008/02/mark-twain-traitor/feed/ 0
Open Access in 2006 /blog/2007/01/open-access-in-2006/ /blog/2007/01/open-access-in-2006/#comments Tue, 02 Jan 2007 20:43:49 +0000 http://muninn.net/blog/2007/01/open-access-in-2006.html Continue reading Open Access in 2006]]> Peter Suber has summed up the Open Access developments for 2006 in the most recent issue of his OA newsletter. You can view the article on his OA blog: Open Access Newsletter 1/2/07. While I haven’t been keeping up with all the changes he mentions in the report, when summed up it is clear that a lot of fantastic progress has been made in the past year, which includes a rapid growth in OA Mandates, Hybrid OA journals, fully OA journals, OA archiving, OA text repositories like Google and Microsoft books, a gradual shift in funding from toll-access journal subscriptions to OA journal publication fees, governments mandating OA for their data, the rise of peer reviewed wikis, the continuing growth in importance of blogs as sources of information, and so on.

Peter Suber takes a look at the long-term progress of the OA movement and sums up his thoughts:

There are roughly three phases for a movement like ours. First, it’s known only to a small group of activists and opponents. Second, familiarity explodes and lots of newcomers start to think and talk about it, not necessarily with good understanding. Third, pretty much all the stakeholders know about it even if they don’t understand it or haven’t made up their minds about it. In my estimation, we entered Phase Two in early 2004 and we started entering Phase Three in 2006. Phase Three is by no means the finish line; the open source movement has been in Phase Three for many years and is still widely misunderstood and slow to make critical gains. And we’re not yet fully in Phase Three. I suspect that nearly all journals and journal publishers have heard of OA, and that the percentage is about as high among funders of research. There are people knowledgeable about OA in almost every university and academic library in the world. But familiarity among professional researchers is still woefully low and good understanding is even further behind.

Regrettably, progress towards OA has been slowest in my own field of humanities. There has been some progress, however. Here is his summary of the developments on this front:

The slowest progress toward OA has been in the humanities, but in 2006 we saw significant acceleration. The US National Endowment for the Humanities adopted a policy to favor applications that promise OA for their results. The long-awaited report from the American Council of Learned Societies not only recommended OA for the humanities, but recommended OA mandates by funders and supportive actions by universities. The EU funded the Digital Research Infrastructure for the Arts and Humanities (DARIAH). The OA Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy took large strides toward building its endowment. MediaCommons began to self-assemble as a cooperative OA book press for the humanities. The Karman Center for Advanced Studies in the Humanities at the University of Bern committed itself to OA for all its future projects. The Task Force on Electronic Publication for the American Philological Association and Archaeological Institute of America recommended that American classicists self-archive and may later recommend that American classics journals convert to OA. Eight classicists issued an open letter to colleagues calling for more OA in the field. Canada’s Social Science and Humanities Research Council reaffirmed its support for OA, though it still stops short of a mandate. JISC and two of the UK Research Councils –the Arts and Humanities Research Council (AHRC), and the Engineering and Physical Sciences Research Council (EPSRC)– are extending the UK’s e-Science program to the arts and humanities. The AHRC is covered by the general RCUK commitment to OA but is still deciding on the exact form of its own policy. The British Academy wrote a report showing how UK copyright law hindered scholarship in the humanities and social sciences. The Modern Language Association recommended tenure reforms to encourage digital publication and departmental rewards for it. And there was wider recognition, approaching a consensus, that the journal pricing crisis in the sciences is a major cause of the monograph crisis in the humanities –and that OA will help both.

My own feeling is that there has to be a greater recognition of and accepted place for a wider variety of the types of contributions scholars can make. It seems to me that currently that the main forms recognized as productive scholarship are: full monograph, chapter in an edited volume, full length journal article; and to a lesser extent: conference paper, translation work, and book reviews. I think that the new mediums we have available to us to spread the results of our research should spark some new thinking and new appreciation for those who make valuable scholarly contributions in a range of new formats, lengths, and mediums.

]]>
/blog/2007/01/open-access-in-2006/feed/ 0
A Response to Sion Touhig’s “How the Anti-copyright Lobby Makes Big Business Richer” /blog/2006/12/a-response-to-sion-touhig-on-his-how-the-anti-copyright-lobby-makes-big-business-richer/ /blog/2006/12/a-response-to-sion-touhig-on-his-how-the-anti-copyright-lobby-makes-big-business-richer/#comments Sat, 30 Dec 2006 01:18:59 +0000 http://muninn.net/blog/2006/12/a-response-to-sion-touhig-on-his-how-the-anti-copyright-lobby-makes-big-business-richer.html Continue reading A Response to Sion Touhig’s “How the Anti-copyright Lobby Makes Big Business Richer”]]> I just read Sion Touhig‘s article “How the Anti-copyright Lobby Makes Big Business Richer” on the Register, and I found it deeply problematic, even if I sympathize with the cause he wants to defend: empowering and preserving the livelihoods of freelance professionals. See also his posting at his weblog here. From his opening:
“I’m a freelance professional photographer, and in recent years, the internet ‘economy’ has devastated my sector. It’s now difficult to make a viable living due to widespread copyright theft from newspapers, media groups, individuals and a glut of images freely or cheaply available on the Web.”

Throughout his article Touhig argues that “media democracy” and “citizen journalism,” aggregated free content, Copyleft, Creative Commons etc. has destroyed the little man’s business and, if passed, the Orphan Works Bill will also rob the little man of his ability to defend his copyright.

As I understand it, the basic system works something like. You create something—a photograph, say—and find that it, having value, can be sold, or licensed, for a certain amount to certain companies or directly to individuals. Its eventual price, if it can be sold, is determined by any number of factors, including the demand for your kind of creative work and supply of other cheaper or free content. Your copyright to this work, certainly not a divinely bestowed right, is at least nominally protected by the laws of a society which believes that the protection of a creative work will, in the end, encourage its people to create more such content in the future.

We find ourselves in a situation now where people of lesser talent, dedication, or financial means (for surely you need at least one, if not two of these three to succeed as a photojournalist) can easily share what we produce with the entire world. Our motivations may be many. Some of those who share what they create, or contribute it to large news corporations or other websites, may hope that they can eventually develop their art into a future career. However, many if not most of people are motivated out of the desire for fame or out of altruism—out of the sincere hope that what they created might be enjoyed or found useful by someone else out there.

Touhig’s article insults those people. It belittles that desire, and it reflects a bitterness about change which is found everywhere and in every generation.

No one is forcing Touhig to use a Creative Commons license. No major corporation is the malevolent puppet-master of the Copyleft movement. These are tools, admirable ones in my opinion, which have in mind not just the producers of content (including both those who wish to profit and those who do not wish to profit from their creative work) but the consumers of content. It gives them both a wonderful set of choices related to how they distribute, use, and modify creative works. In the case of the Creative Commons, it is designed to compliment, not replace, copyright protections.

Touhig is perhaps accurate in, and I am in no position to challenge, his claims about the specific changes within his industry that relate to the increasing difficulties of photojournalists to charge certain amounts for their work or be paid certain amounts to be dedicated to their craft. However, he is completely off the mark when he says that supporters of the various movements above are the “unwitting allies, or shills” of big business. If individual copyright holders have few means to protect their copyright by legal challenges, this is hardly the fault of the Creative Commons movement or Flickr or OhMyNews. If the photojournalist’s photographs are not selling at the same price they used to because there is a sudden flood of cheap alternatives created by people who have no profit motive, it is hardly appropriate to chide the charitable for giving away their content. If the consumer is satisfied with the less skillfully snapped photo, the less grammatically correct article, the goofy home video, or even the factually imperfect article on OhMyNews, WikiNews, etc. it is disingenuous for an elitist photographer to lament the world’s decline in standards by criticizing the movements which make it possible for us all to easily share content.

I used to put together some free macintosh software which I host foolsworkshop.com. My creations are all but useless now but there was a time when at least one of the free programs I created competed favorably with other commercial and shareware software out there. Before the rise of the internet amateur freeware developers such as myself did not have the means to distribute our creations. Other software developers, large and small sold their products via catalogs and shops. When a freeware product is well done, and it offers a comparable or least nearly comparable feature set with a shareware or commercial option, it out-competes the latter. Touhig’s position in his article is comparable to a small-time shareware developer accusing people like me of being the shill or unwitting ally of the commercial software companies. “You bourgeois running dog scum, how dare you give away your labor? What about proles like me who make a living out of this? What about my labor? How dare you undersell sell me with your free software. Don’t you see how this plays into the hands of the capitalists?”

All I can say to Touhig is that I hope he thinks through his position again and reflects on the two successful approaches that both small and big businesses (after all, things like Youtube started as a small business) have taken in response to these new developments. When they can, businesses try to co-opt these energies for its own benefit. When they can’t, they resist, with all their legal, lobbying, and coercive power any attempt to dilute their copyrighted assets. The fact that they can do the latter far better than any individual artist or professional is a matter of course. That is why movements such as the Creative Commons and those supporting serious copyright reforms need to be organized, committed, and highly vigilant in order to prevent a stifling of the very forces of creative energy that the internet has unleashed. However, Touhig completely misses the fact that creative professionals stand a much better chance, if not an equal chance, in the former approach—competing with large corporations when it comes to making use of these new developments for their own benefit. Individuals can adapt faster than corporations. This will require a change of thinking on their part; a change of business model; a change of their whole sales philosophy. A failure to do so may indeed, as Touhig predicts, lead to the destruction of his kind. The onus, however, is on him and professionals like him to take the initiative and adapt.

]]>
/blog/2006/12/a-response-to-sion-touhig-on-his-how-the-anti-copyright-lobby-makes-big-business-richer/feed/ 5
Populating the Past /blog/2005/01/populating-the-past/ /blog/2005/01/populating-the-past/#comments Mon, 10 Jan 2005 00:32:10 +0000 http://muninn.net/blog/2005/01/populating-the-past.html Continue reading Populating the Past]]> I have recently finished a fairly close reading of David Harlan’s The Degradation of American History and some articles by Thomas L. Haskell on “objectivity” in the practice of history. Below are some of my own comments and criticism on them. Because the article is around ten pages when printed out, you can also download a PDF version of this essay here.

No historian can erase her own presence from the history she writes. In fact, it is far less common these days to find historians who claim we should even try. There was perhaps a time when the individual voice, the motives, and the personal choices that historians make in pursuing their craft might seemed to irreversibly soil a work of otherwise immaculate and timeless perfection if they ever leaked to the surface. Now, if anything, the reverse tendency has gained sway. To conceal the inevitable touch of the historian is either seen as a form of deceit—aimed as much at ourselves as it is at others—or it is a function of our language and our times.

With a historicist’s realization that, “History does not belong to us, we belong to it,” we inevitably question what objectivity means in the absence of timelessness.1 The more embedded we recognize ourselves to be in the concerns of the present, the legacies of our past, and the more enslaved to language we find ourselves, the more our foggy window looking out onto history seems like a fun house mirror. Its distorted reflection is enough to haunt some of us in our nightmares, for in its returning gaze we see the abyss of nihilism and a relativist’s despair.

All is not lost, say some, and even our own temporally and linguistically embedded natures can still claim some form of lordship over the past. With a belief in a modest progressivism, an ever so subtle condescension towards any and all that preceded us, we may still salvage the integrity of our research. If we believe that if we cannot fully grasp our own bounds and limitations, we can at least judge the work of those historians who came before us with a modicum of clarity. We are professionals who are confident that our work is the best that has yet to emerge. We are blessed not only with more facts to compare but more perspectives to incorporate into an ever so slightly richer and more complete—if ever incomplete—account.

What should happen however, if this confidence in our own progress is completely torn from us? What if the ever-growing storehouse of facts and ever-proliferating perspectives have as often torn down our foundations as it has led to something creatively synthetic, constructive, and unquestionably superior?

If our foggy window does not look out at all the past at once, perhaps it is more like a train of passengers all continually repeating the same journey but seated in various parts of a segregated train. We are all peering out foggy windows of different sizes and watching two very different landscapes pass quickly by us on opposite sides of the train. We sleep and eat at different times, missing the view as we do. Some of us compare notes, some of us don’t, but unfortunately for us, even the landscape itself changes ever so slightly each time we make the journey. Objects drop in and out of sight from the train’s path or are obscured by mists or the blinding light of a rising sun. Or perhaps it is mostly the weather, but even the hills, they wear away.

This, a reformed moderate historian like Thomas L. Haskell, can claim, is far cry from the glorious construction scene in a valley of Shinar. There we once sought to, “build a tower with its top in the sky, to make a name for ourselves; else we shall be scattered all over the world.”2 Scholars like Haskell gladly admit they do not believe that, “each scholar contributes his brick to a steadily accumulating edifice of unchallengeable knowledge…”3 Instead, finding ourselves scattered all over the world, we seek most of all to speak to each other.
For Haskell, this means that historians must adopt the virtue of “detachment” (a poorly chosen word) which, “functions…not by draining us of passion, but by helping to channel our intellectual passions in such a way as to insure collision with rival perspectives.” If our work cannot serve eternity, let it at least serve each other. It is this literal collision between rivals which will give birth to something new, or at least the death of something old.

This collision is achieved through powerful argument. By its construction and the “detachment” which helps us anticipate a rival’s objections we may show a deep respect for our opponents. “Nothing is more rhetorically powerful than this,” says Haskell, and we will thus have the power to move and persuade those who read it.4 In this way Haskell has interestingly united rhetoric and logic. It is logic, in the form of powerful argument, together with the “detachment” to anticipate counter-argument, which to Haskell are the royal couple of rhetoric. When these are then combined with the virtue of honesty, we can ward against any attempts at sophistry. Haskell’s epistemological vocabulary, now tied as it is to the vague currency of Aristotelian virtue ethics, is already a significant retreat from the bolder correspondence theories of old. However, to go too far and deny the virtue of detachment, “is to defame the species.”5

The defamation of our species, or rather, the degradation of history is not, for the intellectual historian David Harlan, due to any rejection of detachment. In his book The Degradation of American History, Harlan throws Haskell into the pit of moderate pragmatists and professionalists together with James Kloppenberg, David Hollinger, and Joyce Appleby. There they are treated like gutless traditionalists who run for metaphysical cover as soon as their initial concessions to critical theory reveal any consequences.

For David Harlan, the degradation of history hasn’t come, as an unsuspecting reader might have assumed from the title or even the introduction, from the epistemological plunder of poststructuralism. Harlan has no serious quarrel with the theories rejected by both traditional reconstructionists, who believe in an unproblematic historical reconstruction of the past, and the moderates, who either embrace some flavor of pragmatism or the conventions of an intellectual community. Harlan critiques them both but can often be dismissive of their approaches without giving them extended consideration. He opens his discussion of the Appelby et al. approach in Telling the Truth About History by saying that, “reading their account is something like watching a collection of geese try to hatch a duck’s egg—uneventful, as it turns out, but not altogether uninstructive.”6 He will only be persuasive in his handling of these approaches with those of us who already have deep doubts about them. However, I get the impression that these chapters serve more to sever his own connection to these thinkers who see history primarily as a battle between “objective” historians, however defined, and crazed relativists on the other.

What makes Harlan’s account so refreshing is that he is much more interested in what history we can create in the wake of these theoretical battles. In other words, how did these theoretical changes in the field affect actual intellectual history writing (the field he usually restricts himself to) and what kind of intellectual history should we write in the future? Many younger students of history, such as myself, are heavily influenced by poststructuralist theory and the sometimes destructive historiography it has bred. However, many of us are wondering how we are supposed to pick up the pieces. How are we supposed to create something fresh and new in its aftermath?

For Harlan, the real battle is not between reconstructionists, moderates, and poststructuralists—a battle that for him is essentially over. He redirects his attack along a different axis: the contrast between “contextualist” approaches to history and “presentist” approaches that aren’t afraid of decontextualizing or recontextualizing writers of the past. He decides emphatically in favor of the latter, and wants us to regenerate history as a practice of moral reflection. Stop this nonsense about putting everything into its historical context or reducing everything to a one-dimensional hegemonic discourse, and let us unashamedly pursue (intellectual) history as a creative and constructive way to confront our present day problems. “History is a line we ourselves must rig up, to a past we ourselves must populate.”7 In this conclusion to the introduction, the skeptic who excuses herself briefly from the euphoric celebration of historical creativity may want to ask if there are any limits at all on this act of “populating.”

While Harlan’s most bitter words are reserved for historians who want to salvage objectivity or a professionalism based on common traditions or practices, his primary target is really “contextualist” and “radical contextualist” historians who occupy both sides of the epistemological divide. Whether it is Quentin Skinner wanting to recover an author’s “primary intentions,” by immersing ourselves in their times, Sacvan Bercovitch’s reducing the Puritan (and in turn all American) imagination to its fundamental substructure, or the influence of Foucault on a generation of discourse historians, all of these approaches share something in common. Instead of connecting the writings of the past directly to our own and drafting (Harlan uses the word “adopting”) an “ancestor” for participation in an anachronistic but richly creative intellectual dialogue about values, these approaches all seem more concerned with identifying the language, influences and environment of a writer in their historical context. This approach to intellectual history favors a form of analysis that encourages students to read “complex texts as if they were bills of lading,”8 and asks intellectual historians to participate in a, “revolution that devoured its own subjects, for ‘the history of discourse’ ended up reducing earlier thinkers to little more than place markers in a profusion of proliferating discourses.”9

Interestingly, Harlan denounces this contextualist approach not so much by refutation, which would perhaps please the likes of Thomas Haskell, but by a different rhetorical move, “It is a history that exposes our limitations but does nothing to help us transcend them; it reveals our depleted imagination but does nothing to nourish our potential.”10 Harlan believes that our fascination with historical context, despite the deep political convictions which often motivate the discourse historian’s desire to “unmask” the hegemonies of the past are simply not as useful (an idea itself deeply impregnated by pragmatist influences) for us in dealing with the problems of our own current times. For him, such approaches use an, “impoverished notion of hegemony that blights whatever it touches.”11 Even when poststructuralist approaches to history give voice to the unheard, deconstruct previously essentialist identities, expose the fiction of a timeless canon, and multiply the fragments of our history, Harlan shows how this can often lead to sense of despair over the inability to synthesize.12

Harlan’s dream for intellectual history would have us looking to the past, as we once did, for inspiration and moral reflection. He wants us to find those writers who inspire us and wrench them away from the prison of their own time in order to put them together with other thinkers. He sees great potential for making these writers talk to each other and interrogate each other, though they stretch across time and place. He wants,

A history concerned not with dead authors but with living books, not with returning earlier writers to their historical contexts but with reading historical works in new and unexpected contexts, not with reconstructing the past but with providing the critical medium in which valuable works from the past might survive their past…”12

How would we choose such works? He suggests borrowing the idea of “readerly” (lisible) and “writerly” (scriptable) texts from Barthes, or the distinction between “complex works” and “documents” from Dominick LaCapra, or Frank Kermode’s conception of canonical works whose meanings share a degree of indeterminacy and which have the capacity to let us see things we could not have seen before. From these we might be able to, “patch together a provisional working criterion for identifying the books with which intellectual history might concern itself.”14

Harlan commends a number of writers, such John Patrick Diggins, Henry Louise Gates (who calls the method “productive juxtaposition”), Richard Rorty (who calls it “rational reconstruction”), Elaine Showalter, and Michael Walzer’s Exodus and Revolution for already having the courage to embrace this recontextualizing approach. In fact, most of The Degradation of American History is itself an example of the kind of history Harlan has in mind. Throughout his book he has shamelessly thrown together, much to the annoyance of his critics, an amazing breadth of literary figures like Melville, religious thinkers like Augustine, philosophers from Kant and Hegel to Gadamer, Hayden White, Derrida, and historians of all flavors.15 Even when the connections between them seem incredibly tenuous, Harlan is adamant that historians must, “set out not merely to understand the writers of the past but to reeducate them.”16

Earlier I suggested that the skeptic might want to know what limits there are to Harlan’s imperative to “populate” the past. We might ask the same about the limits of “reeducation.” Harlan spends a whole chapter chronicling Hayden White’s own difficult attempt to respond to critics who claimed his structuralist philosophy of history would permit such outrages as a “comic” history of the Holocaust.17

So where are the limits to be found for Harlan? We have already seen him suggest guidelines for the “adoption” of our intellectual predecessors and the establishment of an openly fictional intra-canonical dialogue. How far can we go in populating or reeducating these adopted giants? “We all know,” he answers, “from our own experience as readers, that certain texts resist certain readings.” This is, I’m afraid, as far as he will go on the matter. There is nothing to be found about what kinds of texts resist what kind of reading. Are they always successful in resistance? Or depending on the time and person, can we “overcome” the resistance of a text in order to read it as we like, if, for example, it was urgently pressing for our present needs?

This return to an epistemological realm is not welcome to Harlan. When he chides Haskell by telling him, “he should stop trying to formulate an abstract, high-level, pseudoscientific theory of historical interpretation and start ransacking the past for men and women whose thoughts and lives exemplify the moral values he considers important…Haskell’s standards for ensuring objectivity would offer precious little help in making choices like these, which are, after all, moral and aesthetic choices.”18 On the last point, he is right to be sure, but there is no reason to suggest why Haskell would disagree. Nor would Max Weber who, in his essays “Science as a Vocation,” and “‘Objectivity’ in Social Sciences and Social Policy” argued that these moral and aesthetic choices, so necessary in determining the object and direction of study, were perfectly compatible with a scholar remarkably similar to Haskell’s “detached” historian who recognizes inconvenient facts.19

Haskell has recently reviewed a collection of papers on this dispute which includes philosopher Richard Rorty’s most recent contribution to the debate.20
Rorty’s position seems to overlap in many ways with Haskell on the very same points that David Harlan has rejected in his consideration of the “professionalists” in The Degradation of American History. In the collection of papers reviewed by Haskell, Historians and Social Values, Rorty allies himself somewhat with Weber scholar Wolfgang Mommsen by agreeing to Mommsen’s use of Wissenschaftliche Distanz, a concept that seems very close to the kind of “detachment” that Haskell called for in his 1990 essay on Peter Novick.21 Rorty, however, sees this as, “another word for what I have been calling honesty—for the ability to distinguish between one’s own moral identity and one’s responsibility to one’s fellow historians, and to one’s readers.”22 This is interesting, since Harlan looks to Rorty’s anti-realist pragmatism for an unfettered freedom to manufacture new dialogues between intellectual predecessors that can be wrenched from their context, and of course, his “critique of objectivity.”23

Rorty’s anti-realism hasn’t changed, but this most recent essay suggests that he doesn’t see this his epistemological skepticism to be incompatible with concepts of detachment and especially honesty which lie at the heart of the professionalist moderate argument for a kind of “objectivity” that Harlan believed to be the critical target of Rorty’s work. Of course, Harlan can claim that Rorty’s earlier works have already been “cast afloat in the water” and that he is free to interpret it freely without reference to its author and his newly elaborated (or changed) views.

However, it is not obvious to me how conceding that the moral element guides the “ransacking” of the past is in any way incompatible with promoting a theory of historical interpretation or a Weberian approach to history. Such a theory might be useful if Harlan is to explain how some works resist some readings. Neither is it entirely clear to me why discourse history, or other forms of contextualist history are necessarily less useful to moral reflection than the recontextualized intellectual dialogue Harlan proposes. “Unmasking” of the past and revealing oppressive discourses where they exist can be described as a form of moral lamentation, a kind of social regret, and can often inspire deep reflection in a reader. I was certainly inspired to this kind of deeply moral reflection on reading a discourse history such as Edward Said’s Orientalism.

As long as we do not descend into complete despair and suggest that we are incapable of escaping from the “immanence” of a particular discourse, cannot the two approaches coexist productively? Must we deny the existence of discursive limits in order to celebrate “writerly” (scriptable) texts and their capacity for indeterminate meanings?
Harlan ridicules Haskell’s adoption of the principles of fairness, honesty, and detachment. It is certainly easy to see how these vague and epistemologically hollow concepts will not salvage the “noble dream” of objective history. However, Harlan has little better to offer in this regard, and as we have seen, Rorty has betrayed him.

In fact, Harlan has his own set of virtues that he wants to promote. Instead of fairness, honesty and detachment, Harlan would have the historian be more like the Muse. He believes that what history needs today are, “alert, responsive, and resourceful readers,”24 who approach their work with a “measure of tact, insight, and thoughtfulness…”25

All of this, however, is to focus too much on inconsistencies in Harlan’s critique of the moderates who have come before him. However, this occupied only the “ground clearing” phase of his work. The laudable goal of The Degradation of American History is to promote a creative and constructive approach to intellectual history and shift the debate away from the waging wars of epistemology. In this, I think he has more than adequately demonstrated the value of a decontextualized consideration of texts. He is right that many historians will balk at abandoning context in favor of a temporally and culturally liberated inter-textual dialogue. However, they might ask, justly I believe, whether we should call this practice, however productive, history.

I have no qualms at all with a total freedom in “populating” the past or in reeducating the heroes of our texts and agree wholeheartedly with Harlan that this has powerful rhetorical capabilities and can change our outlook on the world. The heroes we populate the past with need not have existed at all, “out there” in the “real” past. Harlan gives a perfect example of this, when he makes use of Jorge Luis Borges’s wonderful story “Pierre Menard, Author of the Quixote” to make a point about the absurdity of a radical contextualism.26

The story’s narrator reports on his inspection of the personal files and publications of friend of his, an author named Pierre Menard. The narrator lists in detail all the publications of this completely fictional author which range from “A monograph on Leibniz’s Characteristica universalis” to “A technical article on the possibility of improving the game of chess, eliminating one of the rook’s pawns. Menard proposes, recommends, discusses, and finally rejects this innovation.”27 He details his correspondence with the now deceased author about the latter’s greatest masterpiece: Menard’s incredible word by word rewrite of several chapters of Don Quixote. After initially contemplating the rewriting of the classic by immersing himself in the historical context of the work’s time, and forgetting all that thas happens since, Menard abandons this as being too easy. Instead, he decides to rewrite the work as a man of his own times. While identical in every way to the original classic, the narrator finds the few chapters completed of the new version to be a far richer product. When Menard writes (in words identical to Cervantes) “truth, whose mother is history” the narrator marvels, “History, the mother of truth: the idea is astounding. Menard, a contemporary of William James, does not define history as an inquiry into reality but as its origin. Historical truth, for him, is not what has happened; it is what we judge to have happened.”28

Borges, whose fictional narrator is writing about a fictional author who wrote a fictional book, has written words that Harlan, the historian and philosopher of history himself might have written. Borges, the writer, the essayist, a great literary figure of our own century, has written about exactly the kind recontextualizing work that Harlan admires, for Menard’s fictional rewrite of Don Quixote is read as the product of a new age, a new linguistic and historical context. What then separates the work of historical fiction, the fictional book review, or any of the experimental genres that Borges has boldly explored from the work of a historian? This is a question that Harlan did not answer.

1. Hans-Georg Gadamer’s Truth and Method (New York: Seabury, 1975), 245, cited in David Harlan The Degradation of American History (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1997), 9.
2. Genesis 11:4. Speiser, E. A. trans. The Anchor Bible: Genesis (New York: Doubleday & Company, 1964), 74
3. Thomas L. Haskell, “Objectivity is Not Neutrality: Rhetoric vs. Practice in Peter Novick’s That Noble Dream” History and Theory Vol. 29 No. 2 (May, 1990), 130.
4. Ibid., 135
5. Ibid., 133.
6. David Harlan The Degradation of American History (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1997), 96.
7. Ibid., xxxiii.
8. Ibid., 192.
9. Ibid., 4.
10. Ibid., 45.
11. Ibid., 46.
12. This is especially clear in Chapter 3 on feminist history and the example of Joan Scott. See for example, Ibid., 72.
13. Ibid., 31.
14. Ibid., 19.
15. See both the review by Kerwin Lee Klein in William and Mary Quarterly, 3rd Ser. 56:2, 423, in which the reviewer suspects, “readers will wonder at his claims that Jacques Derrida belongs to the same strain of ‘Augustinian piety’ that runs from Jonathan Edwards through Abraham Lincoln and that the writings of John Calvin prefigure post-structuralism.” and Casey N. Blake in The Journal of American History 86:1 (June 1999), 200, “Traditionalists who cannot abide Jacques Derrida and Michel Foucault and poststructuralists who do not read the Puritans may well wonder how they ended up allies in such an insurgency.” All the reviews, including one in History and Theory 39:3 (October 2000), 405-416 are fairly critical, but often seem to have missed the fact that Harlan is openly practicing what he is preaching, radical though his position may be, that a text, “at the very moment of its inception, has already been cast upon the waters.” Harlan Ibid., 21.
16. Harlan, Ibid., 25.
17. See Ibid., Chapter 5, “The Return of the Moral Imagination” Overall, Harlan is gentle in his critique of Hayden, who has earned a place in the second part of his book, “The Renewal of American Historical Writing.”
18. Ibid., 95.
19. Haskell quotes Weber in “’Objectivity’ in Social Science and Social Policy” on this issue to open his most recent review article, “Objectivity: Perspective as Problem and Solution” History and Theory 43 (October 2004), 341.
20. Thomas L. Haskell “Objectivity: Perspective as Problem and Solution” History and Theory 43 (October 2004), 341.
21. I regret to say that I have not yet gotten a hold of a copy of Joep Leerssen and Ann Rigney eds. Historians and Social Values (Amsterdam: Amsterdam University Press, 2000) so this is based on Haskell’s portrayal and quotes from Rorty’s essay in his revew essay Ibid rather than a reading of Rorty’s essay itself. See Haskell Ibid.,
22. The 1990 essay was mentioned above, Thomas L. Haskell, “Objectivity is Not Neutrality: Rhetoric vs. Practice in Peter Novick’s That Noble Dream” History and Theory Vol. 29 No. 2 (May, 1990). Haskell citing Rorty in “Objectivity: Perspective as Problem and Solution”, 349. On the same page there is a long footnote number 12 in which Haskell details how he believes he differs from Rorty. While in practice they don’t disagree on much, Haskell sides more with a Peirce pragmatism which is ultimately realist at its base. Haskell argues that Rorty has, “done his best to demote [Peirce] from the front ranks of the pragmatic tradition,” in favor of his own more radical anti-realist pragmatism. I think Haskell has never really confronted some of the consequences of poststructuralist theory and believes that he can have his cake an eat it too, as Harlan also claims in Harlan Ibid., 86. If he wants to go back to “business as usual” I think Rorty has a much clearer understanding of how to do this without abandoning all theoretical consistency. The original quote by Rorty is apparently in Leerssen Ibid, 203.
23. Harlan Ibid., 153. “Rorty’s importance for historians rests on two central points: his crtique of objectivity and, growing out of that, his belief that intellectual history is mainly a matter of finding intellectual predecessors and lining them up in chronological order.”
24. Ibid., 192.
25. Ibid., 207.
26. Harlan Ibid., 8.
27. Jorge Luis Borges, Andrew Hurley trans. Collected Fictions (New York: Penguin Putnam, 1998), 89.
28. Ibid., 94.

]]>
/blog/2005/01/populating-the-past/feed/ 2
Rory Litwin: Critique of the Google Library Project /blog/2004/12/rory-litwin-critique-of-the-google-library-project/ /blog/2004/12/rory-litwin-critique-of-the-google-library-project/#comments Sat, 18 Dec 2004 21:43:31 +0000 http://muninn.net/blog/2004/12/rory-litwin-critique-of-the-google-library-project.html Continue reading Rory Litwin: Critique of the Google Library Project]]> My sister just passed on to me a scathing critique of the new project to digitize some or all of the contents of several major research libraries by Google (my own posting on this here). Rory Litwin‘s article, entitled “On Google’s Monetization of Libraries” has almost nothing positive to say about the project and fears that this will spell doom for librarians and the enterprise of truth and knowledge. I found the article completely unconvincing, even if it seems to be motivated by a healthy progressive librarian’s skepticism for mammoth corporations like Google and the darker side of capitalist markets. I address some of his specific points in this entry, but the article’s biggest weakness comes from an assumption that the libraries have sold their books and souls to Google and that this demonic internet giant can now proceed with the destruction of mankind’s common quest for truth.

I believe he is wrong on almost every count, although a final verdict on my own response will have to await more details about the specific agreements between the major research libraries involved and Google. He fails to fully recognize the fact that Google has not muscled its way into the stacks of Harvard, U Michigan, and others to rob them of their treasures – even if, as he says, Google’s “back-room deal” was “not worked out in cooperation with the [broader] library community”. It wasn’t, but it was worked out with a select number of huge libraries who are extremely protective of their holdings. These libraries are powerful agents in this discussion, and at least in Harvard’s case, hardly paragons of democratic virtue. Their key future role in this project are not sufficiently addressed by Litwin.

Overall, I think the article represents the last gasp of a bitter and dying breed of specialists who are either unwilling or unable to adapt to both the technological changes of our time, and on the theoretical level, the problematization of the Enlightenment project of progress and knowledge production. I’m sure that many others in the library community, or more broadly information and knowledge specialists, are more willing to recognize their own failure to enlist the massive public support and financial resources needed to digitize their holdings and confront the significant changes to their profession that a digital information world entails.

What gets lost in Litwin’s article, in which the shadow of a deeply commercialized and inequitable world of knowledge hangs over the pursuit of “truth”, is the fact that we already have a deeply inequitable world of knowledge. As a student at Harvard, but a former student of Columbia, Western Washington University and frequent visitor to Stavanger and Bartlesville libraries I can personally attest to the huge gap in access to resources, both digital and traditional. Harvard’s libraries have exceeded all of my expectations but I am only a very temporary guest at the table of its highly restricted library system. I feel a deep sadness that these resources are not available to everyone. I am delighted that Harvard and other similar institutions are opening up, and if it takes a massive corporation to help them take the first step, then I welcome it with open arms.

I seriously doubt that Harvard and the other libraries have signed away control to the eventual digital collections that result, and that we will likely see competition between commercial companies to provide access under some sort of licensing agreement, and potentially, a non-commercial public-supported alternative once the extremely expensive process of digitizing is complete. I believe that hosting such resources is less expensive than the massive investment of digitizing them, and it will be easier for the library community to mobilize behind a more modest public solution to the former (for public domain materials), than the latter. There will then continue to be room for commercial services which add additional features, for-pay access to copyrighted materials, and so on, as well as room for libraries to continue providing free access to those copyrighted materials they cannot legally host online.

As a side note, my own radical opposition to the current regime of intellectual property law also gives me hope that this will advance the revolutionary cause of copyright reform or, should that fail, at least the rise of a massive underground P2P market for huge databases of books and archives.

The appropriate response to the Google project is not a luddite call to arms, but reflection on why the library community could not launch a huge project like this themselves, followed by serious debate about how librarians can ensure that their considerable skills and knowledge will help guide the future use of these new digital resources, in whatever form they take.

Librarians have won incredibly important legal battles to protect equal and public access to (public library and archive) collections. Though some may not see it in these terms, they are in fact the guardians of a deeply socialist conception of knowledge as a public good. The sooner we get all of them on board for the next generation’s war to implant these values in the digital world and establish the legal foundations to protect them, the less likely that the commercialization of most human knowledge will become a real threat.

Since this posting has already grown a bit long, I’ll address specific points by Litwin in a future update to this posting.

]]>
/blog/2004/12/rory-litwin-critique-of-the-google-library-project/feed/ 1
Testing Theories of Japanese Security Policy /blog/2004/08/testing-theories-of-japanese-security-policy/ /blog/2004/08/testing-theories-of-japanese-security-policy/#comments Sun, 29 Aug 2004 23:37:17 +0000 http://muninn.net/blog/2004/08/testing-theories-of-japanese-security-policy.html Continue reading Testing Theories of Japanese Security Policy]]> Over on the EAIA blog I mentioned and summarized an article in International Security on the US-Japan alliance. I brought it up as a kind of controversial Realist article. Sayaka took the bait and bit a chunk out of the essay in a response she wrote in the next posting. She makes several excellent points about the article, which completely dismisses Constructivist approaches to Japanese security policy in favor of a clean “Passing the Buck” Realist interpretation. Sayaka accuses the author of oversimplifying the opposition with a straw man argument.
It is wrong to assume that Constructivists only look at notions and ideas even if Realists only look at power and the structure of international society.

Third, related to the previous point, the attempt to answer the question “Is [Japan’s policy really about] Pacifism?” by looking at the size of the military is off the point. The questions should be, “Why do[es Japan] not exercise normal military power even though it has acquired a huge military capability?”

]]>
/blog/2004/08/testing-theories-of-japanese-security-policy/feed/ 0
EAIA: Reading the Asian Cup /blog/2004/08/eaia-reading-the-asian-cup/ /blog/2004/08/eaia-reading-the-asian-cup/#comments Thu, 12 Aug 2004 10:15:07 +0000 http://muninn.net/blog/2004/08/eaia-reading-the-asian-cup.html I wrote a rather long winded article about the Asian Cup and the media coverage of its last game. It is posted over at the new EAIA blog.

]]>
/blog/2004/08/eaia-reading-the-asian-cup/feed/ 1